It
is rational to be a freeloader and not donate blood despite being
willing to accept it, despite it being not ethically permissible. In
fact, it is likely more rational to be a freeloader than not. This is
because rationality can be defined as making the best use of reason
or logic. Not donating blood, while still being fully willing to
accept in the case of need, is most rational because it accords with
logical steps. This is because freeloading makes it possible for
someone to potentially reap the benefits of blood donation, without
causing themselves any trouble ever. One would never donate any blood
and would spare themselves of the trouble of physically going to
donate blood and possibly suffering from minuscule side-effects like
temporary dizziness. Moreover, even if the situation arose and that
person required a blood transfusion, they would then accept it and
gain the benefits of it. This is very rational on the part of the
person.
A
person can rely on their fellow citizens to donate blood without ever
doing themselves. That person can then potentially reap the rewards
of his fellow citizens while having never caused any problem or
inconvenience, as donating blood may be perceived to be, unto
himself.
It
is only true when personal benefits and costs are considered. Once
factors, like societal moral and ethical ones, are considered, the
questions becomes more complex and difficult. Once ethics are
included, the question is no longer purely logical. Logically, it
makes sense to do less and get more, which is essentially what the
concept of freeloading is in this context. However, once a ethical
viewpoint is included, it can be seen that not donating blood, but
being willing to accept it in the case of a transfusion, is wrong and
not morally acceptable. This is because it is impossible to justify
that one should accept blood when in need whilst never donating it
themselves, if they are physically capable.
The
fact is that a healthy person, who is physically capable of donating
blood, has a very small chance of ever requiring blood. However, that
same person may be mildly troubled by donating blood, either by small
physical side-effects, like temporary dizziness, or simply by the
less convenient allocation of time (i.e. That person could be doing
something more pleasurable with their time than donating blood).
Moreover, even if that person did eventually need blood, they would
most likely have some because of the goodwill of other people.
Therefore,
when considering the personal benefits, it is completely rational to
not donate blood because the chances of one needing it are smaller
than the potential inconveniences faced when donating it, and because
blood will likely be there for you should you need it.
This
story changes especially when you consider the benefits to others. It
becomes realized that other people can potentially rely on this
resource and that, without donations, these people could suffer
severe consequences. These consequences would not be brought about as
a result of their own doing, but rather because of the fact that
people did not want to donate themselves – a sort of collective
action problem.
If
all people believed that they did not need to donate blood because
someone else would do it for them, then there would be little to no
blood supply. This would cause a tremendous detriment to others
(patients) in need of blood. So, from a societal point of view, not
only is failing to donate blood immoral, it is irrational, too. No
benefits exist to others when a person does not donate blood.
Overall,
it is important to recognize the difference between rational and
ethical. Though freeloading is rational, particularly in personal
circumstances, it cannot be ethical under most circumstances. Also,
it needs to be noted that though freeloading is rational on an
individual level because it spares one from a small chore, it is
completely irrational on a societal one because it fails to produce
any benefits to other people.
It
can be considered ethically wrong to not donate blood for a variety
of reasons, but many scenarios need to be considered before making a
definitive statement. Two major arguments exist to help determine the
morality of donating blood. The first is the beneficence argument.
This argument states that whenever a person has the ability to commit
an act of good, they have a moral obligation to do so.
The
second argument regards the wrongness of freeloading. This argument
focuses more on immorality than morality (the beneficence argument
does the opposite, in a way.) It states that it is ethically wrong,
and makes you a freeloader, to reap the benefits of a collective
good, to which others are contributing to, without contributing to it
yourself. This argument elaborates that someone is only entitled to
as big a portion of the collective good, as they themselves
contributed.
Both
of these reasonings do not apply to everyone. Most notably, a person
who is physically incapable of doing good, as per the beneficence
argument, or a person who is physically incapable of contributing to
the collective good, as per the wrongness of freeloading argument, is
not applicable under the reasonings. These people cannot contribute
because they are simply incapable of doing so for no purposeful
reason (since being sick cannot be intentionally self-imposed or
purposeful).
When
other reasons, like religious ones, come into mind, the arguments
have a divergence in their beliefs. If someone follows the beliefs of
a Jehovah's Witness, then that person is not permitted by their
religion to donate, nor receive, blood. Under the beneficence
argument, the Jehovah's Witness is still subject to donating blood.
This is because blood is essential to life, and can therefore save
the lives of people who need it for a medical reason. Any Jehovah's
Witness, who is physically capable of donating blood thus has an
obligation to donate blood because that provides society with a
collective good and that is then their moral obligation. Under the
alternative argument however, a Jehovah's Witness is not obliged to
donate blood. This is because their religion also prevents them from
accepting blood. This means that a Jehovah's Witness, though they
would never donate blood, would also never accept blood. Therefore,
they would not be freeloading because one is not a freeloader if they
do not contribute to a system they do not use.
In
another scenario, where the blood supply is already large and
sufficient, the arguments have reversed stances. Under the
beneficence argument, this scenario would not require anyone to
donate blood. This is because their particular donation would not
benefit the collective good, and is therefore unnecessary ethically.
However, under the wrongness of freeloading argument, a person would
still be required to donate blood if they ever need to use it. This
is because if they did not donate blood, they would be using a public
service without contributing to it equally and thus freeloading.
Selling
blood, instead of donating it leads to a more complex situation.
Under the beneficence argument, if you sell your blood and it ends up
in the same place that it would have if you had donated it, then you
are still providing the same good to people and fulfilling your moral
obligation. However, if your blood ends up in a different place,
where it is not providing a good, or as great a good, to society as
it would have had you simply donated it, then you have not done good
to society and therefore cannot be justified under this argument. For
the wrongness of freeriding argument, the answer it
situation-dependent. If the blood is sold and ends up in the same
place that it will be withdrawn from one day by you should you
require it, then it is not a problem because you are contributing to
the collective good that you are using. Alternatively, if it is sold
and ends up in a different place than the one where you withdraw the
blood you need from, then you are freeriding because you are
withdrawing the blood you need from a place to which you did not
contribute.
In
another scenario one may consider paying someone to donate blood on
their behalf. This is ethically unjustified under the beneficence
argument unless you are physically incapable of donating blood
yourself. Under this viewpoint, you can still do more good if you go
and donate blood by yourself, so if you simply pay someone else to
complete this on your behalf, you are basically motivating that
person to fulfill their moral duty under the beneficence argument, as
oppose to actually satisfying your own. If however, you were
incapable of donating blood for physical reasons and paid someone to
donate on your behalf, then you are doing a good for society in the
best way you possibly can, so you would justified as fulfilling your
moral obligation. Alternatively, under the wrongness of freeloading
argument, you would be backed-up ethically by paying someone to
donate on your behalf. This is because if you ever required blood
yourself, you would still have contributed to the collective good,
albeit in a financial way. That financial way would have led to the
same result as you physically donating the blood yourself and you
could not be considered a freeloader.
Finally,
under the beneficence argument, participating at a blood clinic as a
trained medical professional would not exempt you from donating blood
yourself. This is because this argument requires that any good that
ca be performed by an individual be performed in order for that
individual to satisfy their moral obligation. So, if someone can both
participate in a blood donation clinic as a medical professional, and
donate blood, which are both good things, then that person has a
ethical obligation to do both things. Likewise, under the wrongness
of freeloading argument, the person would still not be exempt from
donating blood. This is because if that person requires blood, they
would taking it from a collective good to which they had never
directly contributed to (the only direct contribution would be
donating your blood), thus making them a freeloader.
Donating
blood and being vaccinated are inherently different things. Being
vaccinated for a contagious disease, like the mumps, makes it
significantly less likely that you will get the disease and therefore
be a carrier for it. This means that you will be less likely to make
other people sick. Donating blood, however, is different. By not
donating blood, you are not making anyone sick or worse off, you are
simply making it more difficult for someone who requires blood to get
better. So the difference is that in the vaccination scenario, you
are directly contributing to causing people to be sick and worse off.
In the donating blood scenario, you are simply indirectly making it
more difficult for those who are already sick to improve their
condition. Therefore, it seems sensible to prevent people from
getting others sick and compromising their own health by making
vaccination mandatory. But, it does not seem sensible to mandate
donating blood because that would not prevent people from falling
ill, nor would it compromise the health of healthy people – it
would simply make it far more difficult for people to improve their
health when they require blood.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Any thoughts? Want to tell me something? Start a debate and get talking! Comment below!